Picard's Little Theorem and Twice-Punctured Plane

Introduction

Let $f:\mathbb{C} \to \mathbb{C}$ be a holomorphic function. By Liouville’s theorem, if $f(\mathbb{C})$ is bounded, then $f$ has to be a constant function. However, there is a much stronger result. In fact, if $f(\mathbb{C})$ differs $\mathbb{C}$ from exactly $2$ points, then $f$ is a constant. In other words, suppose $f$ is non-constant, then the equation $f(z)=a$ for all $a \in \mathbb{C}$ except at most one $a$. To think about this, if $f$ is a non-constant polynomial, then $f(z)=a$ always has a solution (the fundamental theorem of algebra). If, for example, $f(z)=\exp(z)$, then $f(z)=a$ has no solution only if $a=0$.

The proof will not be easy. It will not be proved within few lines of obvious observations, either in elementary approaches or advanced approaches. In this post we will follow the later by studying the twice-punctured plane $\mathbb{C} \setminus\{0,1\}$. To be specific, without loss of generality, we can assume that $0$ and $1$ are not in the range of $f$. Then $f(\mathbb{C}) \subset \mathbb{C}\setminus\{0,1\}$. Next we use advanced tools to study $\mathbb{C}\setminus\{0,1\}$ in order to reduce the question to Liouville’s theorem by constructing a bounded holomorphic function related to $f$.

We will find a holomorphic covering map $\lambda:\mathfrak{H} \to \mathbb{C}\setminus\{0,1\}$ and then replace $\mathfrak{H}$ with the unit disc $D$ using the Cayley transform $z \mapsto \frac{z-i}{z+i}$. Then the aforementioned $f$ will be lifted to a holomorphic function $F:\mathbb{C} \to D$, which has to be constant due to Liouville’s theorem, and as a result $f$ is constant.

With these being said, we need analytic continuation theory to establish the desired $\lambda$, and on top of that, (algebraic) topology will be needed to justify the function $F$.

Analytic Continuation

For a concrete example of analytic continuation, I recommend this post on the Riemann $\zeta$ function. In this post however, we only focus on the basic language of it in order that we can explain later content using analytic continuation.

Our continuation is always established “piece by piece”, which is the reason we formulate continuation in the following sense.

Definition 1. A function element is an ordered pair $(f,D)$ where $D$ is an open disc and $f \in H(D)$. Two function elements $(f_1,D_1)$ and $(f_2,D_2)$ are direct continuation of each other if $D_1 \cap D_2 \ne \varnothing$ and $f_1=f_2$ on $D$. In this case we write

The notion of ordered pair may ring a bell of sheaf and stalk. Indeed some authors do formulate analytic continuation in this language, see for example Principles of Complex Analysis by Serge Lvovski.

The $\sim$ relation is by definition reflective and symmetric, but not transitive. To see this, let $\omega$ be the primitive $3$-th root of unity. Let $D_0, D_1,D_2$ be open discs with radius $1$ and centres $\omega^0,\omega^1,\omega^2$. Since the $D_i$ are simply connected, we can always pick $f_i \in H(D_i)$ such that $f_i^2(z)=z$, and $(f_0,D_0) \sim (f_1,D_1)$ and $(f_1,D_1) \sim (f_2,D_2)$ but on $D_0 \cap D_2$ one has $f_2 =-f_0 \ne f_0$. Indeed there is nothing mysterious: we are actually rephrasing the fact that square root function cannot be defined at a region containing $0$.

Definition 2. A chain is a finite sequence $\mathscr{C}$ of discs $(D_0,D_1,\dots,D_n)$ such that $D_{i-1} \cap D_i \ne \varnothing$ for $i=1,\dots,n$. If $(f_0,D_0)$ is given and if there exists function elements $(f_i,D_i)$ such that $(f_{i-1},D_{i-1}) \sim (f_i,D_i)$ for $i=1,\dots,n$, then $(f_n,D_n)$ is said to be the analytic continuation of $(f_0,D_0)$ along $\mathscr{C}$.

A chain $\mathscr{C}=(D_0,\dots,D_n)$ is said to cover a curve $\gamma$ with parameter interval $[0,1]$ if there are numbers $0=s_0<s_1<\dots<s_n=1$ such that $\gamma(0)$ is the centre of $D_0$, $\gamma(1)$ is the centre of $D_n$, and

If $(f_0,D_0)$ can be continued along this $\mathscr{C}$ to $(f_n,D_n)$, we call $(f_n,D_n)$ an analytic continuation of $(f_0,D_0)$ along $\gamma$; $(f_0,D_0)$ is then said to admit an analytic continuation along $\gamma$.

Either way, it is not necessary that $(f_0,D_0) \sim (f_n,D_n)$. However, unicity of $(f_n,D_n)$ is always guaranteed. We will sketch out the proof on unicity.

Lemma 1. Suppose that $D_0 \cap D_1 \cap D_2 \ne \varnothing$, $(D_0,f_0) \sim (D_1,f_1)$ and $(D_1,f_1) \sim (D_2,f_2)$, then $(D_0,f_0) \sim (D_2,f_2)$.

Proof. By assumption, $f_0=f_1$ in $D_0 \cap D_1$, and $f_1=f_2$ in $D_1 \cap D_2$. It follows that $f_0=f_2$ in $D_0 \cap D_1 \cap D_2$, which is open and non-empty. Since $f_0$ and $f_2$ are holomorphic in $D_0 \cap D_2$ and $D_0 \cap D_2$ is connected, we have $f_0 = f_2$ in $D_0 \cap D_2$. This is because on a open connected set $D_0 \cap D_2$, the zero of $f_0-f_2$ is not discrete. Therefore $f_0-f_2$ has to be $0$ everywhere on $D_0 \cap D_2$. $\square$

Theorem 1. If $(f,D)$ is a function element and $\gamma$ is a curve which starts at the centre of $D$, then $(f,D)$ admits at most one analytic continuation along $\gamma$.

Sketch of the proof. Let $\mathscr{C}_1=(A_0,A_1,\dots,A_m)$ and $\mathscr{C}_2=(B_0,B_1,\dots,B_n)$ be two chains that cover $\gamma$. If $(f,D)$ can be analytically continued along $\mathscr{C}_1$ to a function element $(g_m,A_m)$ and along $\mathscr{C}_2$ to $(h_n,B_n)$, then $g_m=h_n$ in $A_m \cap B_n$.

We are also given partitions $0=s_0<s_1<\dots<s_m=s_{m+1}=1$ and $0=t_0<t_1<\dots<t_n=t_{n+1}=1$ such that

and function elements $(g_i,A_i) \sim (g_{i+1},A_{i+1})$ and $(h_j,B_j) \sim (h_{j+1},B_{j+1})$ for $0 \le i \le m-1$ and $0 \le j \le n-1$ with $g_0=h_0=f$. The poof is established by showing that the continuation is compatible with intersecting intervals, where lemma 1 will be used naturally. To be specific, if $0 \le i \le m$ and $0 \le j \le n$, and if $[s_i,s_{i+1}] \cap [t_j,t_{j+1}] \ne \varnothing$, then $(g_i, A_i) \sim (h_j,B_j)$.

The Monodromy Theorem

The monodromy theorem asserts that on a simply connected region $\Omega$, for a function element $(f,D)$ with $D \subset \Omega$, we can extend it to all $\Omega$ if $(f,D)$ can be continued along all curves. To prove this we need homotopy properties of analytic continuation and simply connected spaces.

Definition 1. A simply connected space is a path connected topological space $X$ with trivial fundamental group $\pi_1(X,x_0)=\{e\}$ for all $x_0 \in X$.

The following fact is intuitive and will be used in the monodromy theorem.

Lemma 2. Let $X$ be a simply connected space and let $\gamma_1$ and $\gamma_2$ be two closed curves $[0,1] \to X$ with $\gamma_1(0)=\gamma_2(0)$ and $\gamma_1(1)=\gamma_2(1)$. Then $\gamma_1$ and $\gamma_2$ are homotopic.

Proof. Let $\gamma_i^{-1}$ be the curve defined by $\gamma_i^{-1}(t)=\gamma_i(1-t)$ for $i=1,2$. Then

where $e$ is the identity of $\pi_1(X,\gamma_1(0))$. $\square$

Next we prove the two-point version of the monodromy theorem.

Monodromy theorem (two-point version). Let $\alpha,\beta$ be two points on $\mathbb{C}$ and $(f,D)$ be a function element where $D$ is centred at $\alpha$. Let $\{\gamma_t\}$ be a homotopy class indexed by a map $H(s,t):[0,1] \times [0,1] \to \mathbb{C}$ with the same origin $\alpha$ and terminal $\beta$. If $(f,D)$ admits analytic continuation along each $\gamma_t$, to an element $(g_t,D_t)$, then $g_1=g_0$.

In brief, analytic continuation is faithful along homotopy classes. By being indexed by $H(s,t)$ we mean that $\gamma_t(s)=H(s,t)$. We need the uniform continuity of $H(s,t)$.

Proof. Fix $t \in [0,1]$. By definition, there is a chain $\mathscr{C}=(A_0,\dots,A_n)$ which covers $\gamma_t$, with $A_0=D$, such that $(g_t,D_t)$ is obtained by continuation of $(f,D)$ along $\mathscr{C}$. There are numbers $0=s_0<\dots<s_n=1$ such that

For each $i$, define

The $d_i$ makes sense and is always positive, because $E_i$ is always compact and $A_i$ is an open set. Then pick any $\varepsilon \in (0,\min_i\{d_i\})$. Since $H(s,t)$ is uniformly continuous, there exists a $\delta>0$ such that

We claim that $\mathscr{C}$ also covers $\gamma_u$. To do this, pick any $s \in [s_i,s_{i+1}]$. Then $\gamma_u(s) \in A_i$ because

Therefore by theorem 1, we have $g_t=g_u$. Notice that for any $t \in [0,1]$, there is a segment $I_t$ such that $g_u=g_t$ for all $u \in [0,1] \cap I_t$. Since $[0,1]$ is compact, there are finitely many $I_t$ that cover $[0,1]$. Since $[0,1]$ is connected, we see, after a finite number of steps, we can reach $g_0=g_1$. $\square$

Momodromy theorem. Suppose $\Omega$ is a simply connected open subset of the plane, $(f,D)$ is a function element with $D \subset \Omega$, and $(f,D)$ can be analytically continued along every curve in $\Omega$ that starts at the centre of $D$. Then there exists $g \in H(\Omega)$ such that $g(z)=f(z)$ for all $z \in D$.

Proof. Let $\gamma_0$ and $\gamma_1$ be two curves in $\Omega$ from the centre $\alpha$ of $D$ to some point $\beta \in \Omega$. Then the two-point monodromy theorem and lemma 2 ensures us that these two curves lead to the same element $(g_\beta,D_\beta)$, where $D_\beta \subset \Omega$ is a circle with centre at $\beta$. If $D_{\beta_1}$ intersects $D_\beta$, then $(g_{\beta_1},D_{\beta_1})$ can be obtained by continuing $(f,D)$ to $\beta$, then along the segment connecting $\beta$ and $\beta_1$. By definition of analytic continuation, $g_{\beta_1}=g_\beta$ in $D_{\beta_1} \cap D_\beta$. Therefore the definition

is a consistent definition and gives the desired holomorphic extension of $f$. $\square$

Modular Function

Let $\mathfrak{H}$ be the open upper half plane. We will find a function $\lambda \in H(\mathfrak{H})$ whose image is $E=\mathbb{C} \setminus\{0,1\}$ and is in fact the (holomorphic) covering space of $E$. The function $\lambda$ is called a modular function.

As usual, consider the action of $G=SL(2,\mathbb{Z})$ on $\mathfrak{H}$ given by

Definition 2. A Modular function is a holomorphic (or meromorphic) function $f$ on $\mathfrak{H}$ which is invariant under a non-trivial subgroup $\Gamma$ of $G$. That is, for any $\varphi \in \Gamma$, one has $f \circ \varphi=f$.

In this section, we consider this subgroup:

It has a fundamental domain

Basically, $Q$ is bounded by two vertical lines $x=1$ and $x=-1$ vertically, and two semicircles with centre at $x=\frac{1}{2}$ and $x=-\frac{1}{2}$ with diameter $1$, but only the left part contains boundary points. The term fundamental domain will be justified by the following theorem.

Theorem 4. Let $\Gamma$ and $Q$ be as above.

(a) Let $\varphi_1,\varphi_2$ be two distinct elements of $\Gamma$, then $\varphi_1(Q) \cap \varphi_2(Q) = \varnothing$.

(b) $\bigcup_{\varphi \in \Gamma}\varphi(Q)=\mathfrak{H}$.

(c) $\Gamma$ is generated by two elements

Sketch of the proof. Let $\Gamma_1$ be the subgroup of $\Gamma$ generated by $\sigma$ and $\tau$, and show (b’):

Then (a) and (b’) would imply that $\Gamma_1=\Gamma$ and (b) is proved. To prove (a), one will replace $\varphi_1$ with the identity element and discuss the relationship between $c$ and $d$ for $\varphi_2=\begin{pmatrix}a & b \\ c & d \end{pmatrix}$. To prove (b’), one need to notice that

For $w \in \mathfrak{H}$, by picking $\varphi_0 \in \Gamma$ that maximises $\Im\varphi_0(w)$, only to show that $z=\varphi_0(w) \in \Sigma$ and therefore $w \in \Sigma$.


We are now allowed to introduce the modular function.

Theorem 5. Notation being above, there exists a function $\lambda \in H(\mathfrak{H})$ such that

(a) $\lambda \circ \varphi = \lambda$ for every $\varphi \in \Gamma$.

(b) $\lambda$ is one-to-one on $Q$.

(c) $\lambda(\mathfrak{H})=\lambda(Q)=E=\mathbb{C}\setminus\{0,1\}$.

(d) $\lambda$ has the real axis as its natural boundary. That is, $\lambda$ has no holomorphic extension to any region that properly contains $\mathfrak{H}$.

Proof. Consider

This is a simply connected region with simple boundary. There is a continuous function $h$ which is one-to-one on $\overline{Q}_0$ and is holomorphic in $Q_0$ such that $h(Q_0)=\mathfrak{H}$, $h(0)=0$, $h(1)=1$ and $h(\infty)=\infty$. This is a consequence of conformal mapping theory.

The Schwartz reflection principle extends $h$ to a continuous function on $\overline{Q}$ which is a conformal mapping of $Q^\circ$ (the interior of $Q$) onto the plane minus the non-negative real axis, by the formula

Note the extended $h$ is one-to-one on $Q$, and $h(Q)$ is $E$ defined in (c).

On the boundary of $Q$, the function $h$ is real. In particular,

and that

We now define

for $\varphi \in \Gamma$ and $z \in \varphi(Q)$. This definition makes sense because for each $z \in \mathfrak{H}$, there is one and only one $\varphi \in \Gamma$ such that $z \in \varphi(Q)$. Properties (a) (b) and (c) follows immediately.

Notice $\lambda$ is continuous on

and therefore on an open set $V$ containing $Q$. Cauchy’s theorem shows that $\lambda$ is holomorphic in $V$. Since $\mathfrak{H}$ is covered by the union of the sets $\varphi(V)$ for $\varphi \in \Gamma$, and since $\lambda \circ \varphi = \lambda$, we conclude that $\lambda \in H(\mathfrak{H})$.

Finally, the set of all numbers $\varphi(0)=b/d$ is dense on the real axis. If $\lambda$ could be analytically continued to a region which properly contains $\mathfrak{H}$, the zeros of $\lambda$ would have a limit point in this region, which is impossible since $\lambda$ is not constant. $\square$

We are now ready for the pièce de résistance of this post.

Picard’s Little Theorem

Theorem (Picard). If $f$ is an entire function and if there are two distinct complex numbers $\alpha$ and $\beta$ such that are not in the range of $f$, then $f$ is constant.

The proof is established by considering an analytic continuation of a function $g$ associated with $f$. The continuation will be originated at the origin and validated by monodromy theorem. Then by Cayley’s transformation, we find out the range of $g$ is bounded and hence $g$ is constant, so is $f$.

Proof. First of all notice that without loss of generality, we assume that $\alpha=0$ and $\beta=1$, because otherwise we can replace $f$ with $(f-\alpha)/(\beta-\alpha)$. That said, the range of $f$ is $E$ in theorem 5. There is a disc $A_0$ with centre at $0$ so that $f(A_0)$ lies in a disc $D_0 \subset E$.

For every disc $D \subset E$, there is an associated region $V \subset \mathfrak{H}$ such that $\lambda$ in theorem 5 is one-to-one on $V$ and $\lambda(V)=D$; each such $V$ intersects at most two of the domains $\varphi(Q)$. Corresponding to each choice of $V$, there is a function $\psi \in H(D)$ such that $\psi(\lambda(z))=z$ for all $z \in V$.

Now let $\psi_0 \in H(D_0)$ be the function such that $\psi_0(\lambda(z))=z$ as above. Define $g(z)=\psi_0(f(z))$ for $z \in A_0$. We claim that $g(z)$ can be analytically continued to an entire function.

If $D_1$ is another disc in $E$ with $D_0 \cap D_1 \ne \varnothing$, we can choose a corresponding $V_1$ so that $V_0 \cap V_1 \ne \varnothing$. Then $(\psi_0,D_0)$ and $(\psi_1,D_1)$ are direct analytic continuations of each other. We can proceed this procedure all along to find a direct analytic continuation $(\psi_{i+1},D_{i+1})$ of $(\psi_i,D_i)$ with $V_{i+1} \cap V_i \ne 0$. Note $\psi_i(D_i) \subset V_i \subset \mathfrak{H}$ for all $i$.

Let $\gamma$ be a curve in the plane which starts at $0$. The range of $f \circ \gamma$ is a compact subset of $E$ and therefore $\gamma$ can be covered by a chain of discs, say $A_0,\dots,A_n$, so that each $f(A_i)$ is in a disc $D_i \subset E$. By considering function elements $\{(\psi_{i},D_i)\}$, composing with $f$ on each $D_i$ (this is safe because $f$ is entire), we get an analytic continuation of $(g,A_0)$ along the chain $(A_0,\dots,A_n)$. Note $\psi_i \circ f(A_i) \subset \psi_i(D_i) \subset \mathfrak{H}$ again.

Since $\gamma$ is arbitrary, we have shown that $(g,A_0)$ can be analytically continued along every curve in the plane. The monodromy theorem implies that $g$ extends to an entire function. Thus proving our claim given before.

Note the range of the extended $g$ on every possible $A_i$ has range lying inside $\mathfrak{H}$. Therefore $g(\mathbb{C}) \subset \mathfrak{H}$. It follows that

has range in the unit disc. By Liouville’s theorem, $h$ is a constant function. Thus $g$ is constant too.

Now we move back to $f$ by looking at $A_0$. Since $\psi_0$ is one-to-one on $f(A_0)$ and $A_0$ is not empty and open, $f(A_0)$ has to be a singleton. Thus $f$ is constant on $A_0$. If we represent $f$ as a power series on a disc lying inside $A_0$, we see $f$ has to be a constant. $\square$

Note we have also seen that the range of a non-constant function cannot be half of a plane. But this result is useless because we can find two points on a large chunk of a plane after all.

Reference

  • Walter Rudin, Real and Complex Analysis.
  • Tammo tom Dieck, Algebraic Topology.

Picard's Little Theorem and Twice-Punctured Plane

https://desvl.xyz/2023/09/18/picard-little/

Author

Desvl

Posted on

2023-09-18

Updated on

2023-09-18

Licensed under

Comments